Thursday, May 08, 2008

socially constructed vs natural disadvantages

Most analytic philosophers are not sympathetic to the "social model of disability" that is often ascribed to "extremist disability advocates", namely the idea that disabilities should be conceived as the result of a social construction and should be understood in analogy to being the member of a discriminated minority. They tend to agree on a moderate position according to which disability differs from social discrimination, even if most disabilities cause an additional disadvantage via social discrimination. Most analytic philosophers reject the social model of disability because they think that the distinction between a purely socially constructed disadvantage and a disability has some normative validity.

Glover, for instance, writes that

All disabilities involve functional limitation. This contrasts with purely socially constructed disadvantages - for instance, those facing members of ethnic minorities in a racist society. […] In theory, social output is not in the same way essential for something to be a disability. Robinson Crusoe, alone on his island and unable to walk properly after a stroke, would still be disabled.
What pisses me off about such examples is that they wrongly suggest that they illustrate a normatively relevant distinction. This is not the case. I'm not just complaining that disadvantage derives, in most cases, from the combined effect of social discrimination and functional impairment, which Glover would not deny. I complain because the use of this example suggests that we can make a distinction that in reality we cannot make.

The example wrongly suggests that we can use a "Robinson Crusoe" test as the litmus test for distinguishing authentic disabilities from cases of purely socially constructed disadvantage. Take the example of deafness. According to the "Robinson Crusoe-test" deafness is an authentic disability: "Robinson Crusoe, alone on his island and unable to hear properly after a stroke, would still be disabled." Sound enough, but so what? The reason why a deaf Robinson Crusoe is disabled is that he lives in a very special social environment, an environment in which he cannot cooperate with other human beings. It would just be wrong to infer that, since deafness is an impairment to human flourishing in the Robinson Crusoe environment, then the disadvantages to which it leads in other environments are purely socially constructed.

Consider this example: having a white skin is an authentic disability in many natural environments. "Robinson Crusoe, alone on his island, without clothes, with his melanin-poor white skin, would still be disabled." (The relevant comparison, here, is with a black-skin Robinson Crusoe, who would be able to stay under the sun for longer time without burning is skin.) Now imagine a society, in cold climate, where black people are more powerful than white and black people treat white just like blacks were treated by whites in nineteen century America. Should we conclude that the disadvantage attached in this society to being white is not purely socially constructed, just because whiteness counts as a disability in the Robinson Crusoe case?

More generally, it is not at al obvious at all that the Robinson Crusoe case is relevant to judge whether something is a disability or a "purely socially constructed disadvantage", because in most cases there is no useful parallelism between this case and the cases in which people live in a society.

priority of fair equality of opportunity over the difference principle

Someone may object:
"What you say here is absurd! It makes no sense to say "A society that does not violate the principle of fair equality of opportunity can hardly manage to discriminate people in relation to their skin color (that is, treat skin color as a relevant qualification for a social position) if it is also, at the same time, a society that satisfies the difference principle", as you do. For the principle of fair equality of opportunity already rules out the possibility of discrimination on the basis of skin color and one does not need to consider distributive consequences at all. In Rawls, fair equality of opportunity has lexical priority over the difference principle."

This appears correct. But there are some logical difficulties. Rawls's explanation of the principle is the following:

Those with similar abilities and skills should have similar life chances. More specifically, assuming that there is a distribution of natural assets, those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have the same willingness to use them, should have the same prospects of success regardless of their initial place in the social system.
The problem is how one defines what counts as an ability or as a skill in the first place. According to Rawls, the fact that someone has a valuable talent or ability is not a mere "natural" fact: whether something counts as a talent depends from what a society values; and what a society values depends from the kind of institutions that govern it. In a society that is governed by just institution different things would count as talents, than in a society governed by unjust ones.

It might be claimed that it makes no sense to call skin color an "ability" or a "skill". But what counts as "ability" or "skill" depends very much on the sort of interactions people have. Consider beauty for example: is beauty a "skill"? Well, for certain jobs it certainly counts as one. Now consider a society of white racists where black people are a tiny minority: people in this society might consider blacks not to be beautiful. In a racist society there might be jobs for which beauty is a skill, and since black people are considered ugly (that is, are ugly, relative to that society), black people will not be qualified for positions where beauty is considered a qualification. In this society, black and white people do not have equal chances to occupy the same social positions. This is certainly a bad thing. But is it a violation of fair equality of opportunity, as Rawls defines it? Can one move an objection against it solely by considering the principle of fair equality of opportunity?

If one takes into account imaginary psychologies, the point becomes even clearer. Imagine creatures for whom a strong reactions of fear and disgust against people with a different color of skin is hard-wired, so that it is always more difficult for them to cooperate with a person of a different skin. It follows that in a firm where black people are the majority, the hiring of a white person would be ceteribus paribus less productive than the hiring of a black one. If a majority of black people works in the the majority of firms (just because they are the majority of the population, let us suppose), then a white person would have less chances than a black person to occupy the same social position. In such a society, would this fact constitute a violation of fair equality of opportunity? Would it not be more appropriate to say, for that society, that blackness counts as a skill or as an ability, namely, the ability to cooperate without creating disgust or fear?

The point can be made in a different way: Rawls says that the principle of fair equality of opportunity has lexical priority over the difference principle. What does this means? By lexical priority is usually meant that the principle that has lexical priority has to be satisfied before the other one. Now consider the principle of fair equality of opportunity: what can it mean that it must be satisfied before the difference principle? Perhaps it means that institutions should be designed, first, in such a way that those with similar talents and willingness to apply them will have an equal chance to occupy the same (or similar) social positions; and that one must make sure that this is the case before one considers whether the basic institutional structure of society satisfies the difference principle. The problem with this interpretation is that, in a Rawlsian perspective, it is impossible to say who are people that have similar talents before institutions are in place so that freely interacting people bounded by these institutions can define what they can value as talents in the first place. This is because whether a characteristic counts as a talent or not depends from the decisions taken freely by people legitimately interacting within the boundaries set by just institutions. So there is no way to identify talents prior to the design of a just basic structure. And a just basic structure is one that, among other things, satisfies the difference principle. So, what can count as a talent or as an ability in a JUST society is determined also by the overall shape of its institutions: a talent or an ability in a just society is whatever people end up valuing as a talent or as an ability if they live in a society where individual freedoms are respected, where people with equal talents have equal chances to obtain similar positions, and where cooperation works to the advantage of the worst off members of society (the difference principle).

Since one cannot know what is a talent or an ability before one has designed institutions, the satisfaction of the principle of fair equality of opportunity must be understood as the satisfaction of a formal condition: for anything that counts as an ability or a talent in a given society, people who are born with the same ability or talent and manifest the same willingness to use them should have equal chance to obtain similar social positions, no matter their starting place in society. What I am pointing out is that it is impossible to determine whether the principle of fair equality of opportunity is satisfied by a given institutional arrangement independently from considering whether the difference principle is satisfied.

Let us come back to discrimination against black people. I made an example of a society where black people are considered ugly. In this society it is not clear that a black man's reduced opportunity to occupy places where beautiful people are sought constitutes a violation of fair equality of opportunity. However, it is quite unlikely that a just society can ever be like this. The color of the skin is not correlated to other trait that lead to high marginal productivity, such as organization skills, fantasy, determination, intelligence etc. A productive society is one where people who have such skills occupy places of responsibility and power. It must be a society that treats organization skills, intelligence, determination, etc as talents and abilities. In a regime of fair equality of opportunity, if the population is equally divided into black and whites, this society will have as many black as white people in positions of responsibility and power (since fair equality guarantees that people that have the same talents and will will occupy similar positions, and skin color is not correlated to these talents and will). In such a society it is very psychologically unlikely that people can develop the racist attitudes that bring them to find black people ugly.

What the example shows is that we can discover violations of fair equality of opportunity only after what counts as a talent is defined. But what counts as a talent in a society depends from what will be treated as a valid qualification for a place of responsibility and power in a society where equal liberties and both fair equality of opportunity and the difference people are respected. Only certain combinations of attitudes towards what counts as a talent or as an ability are compatible with all these conditions simultaneously. This ensures for example that discrimination on the basis of skin color will never be legitimate in a just society.

Does that mean that the principle of fair equality of opportunity cannot be lexically prior to the difference principle? I do not agree. I believe that the lexical priority of the principle of fair equality of opportunity over the difference principle must be understood as the priority of a formal "side-constrain". What it tells us is that among all the basic structures of society that satisfy the difference principle (and the equal liberties) the only legitimate ones are those where people that have similar talents (whatever talents are, in those society) have the same chances to occupy similar positions. If people of equal talents and will do not have the same chances of getting to similar positions, despite the class in which they are born and develop until the age of reasons, than that society is unjust, no matter whether cooperation goes to the advantage of the worst off individuals. Notice that to test whether this condition is satisfied one begins by checking whether cooperation satisfies the difference principle (and the equal freedoms) and then rules out as illegitimate all those societies where people that are similar in what counts as a talent or as a qualification in those societies do not have equal chances to occupy similar positions. This is the sense in which fair equality of opportunity has lexical priority.

Wednesday, May 07, 2008

Rawls and talents: third reflection

The third reflection concerns whether a just society (just, that is, according to Justice as Fairness) can be a society in which disabled people, or better people with certain deviations from standard human functioning can all be among the worst off (in terms of expectations of primary goods).


Consider deviations from standard human functioning such as deafness or a particularly short height (notice that such deviations do not impair a person's capacity human functioning necessariy, or at least it would be controversial to say so). Let us imagine a society that treats a good hear or tallness as qualifications for many jobs, systematically. (It should not be a society so difficult from ours.) In other words, it would discriminate against short and deaf people (in the morally neutral sense of "discriminate", meaning "distinguish from the rest and reject", not "illegitimately or immorally distinguish from the rest and reject"). This society may:
1. fulfill the clause of fair equality of opportunity: people with similar talents/abilities and willingness to use them would have similar life chances. In a society characterized by the total lack of attention for the special needs deriving from deviations from standard human functioning, deaf and short people will lack an important talent or ability (for that society) and all end up with little life opportunities; [remember that Rawlsian talents are society-relative]
2. contain institutions that are not improvable from the standpoint of the difference principle: it might be that no change in its institutions can reduce inequality without worsening the position of the worst off members of society, measured in terms of income and wealth.

Notice the opposition with the case of racial discrimination. A society that does not violate the principle of fair equality of opportunity can hardly manage to discriminate people in relation to their skin color (that is, treat skin color as a relevant qualification for a social position) if it is also, at the same time, a society that satisfies the difference principle. For, as far as our knowledge of production and exchange tells us, it might be possible to either reduce inequality or to raise the life-prospects of the worst off members by simply allowing people with the usual productive talents (productivity, organization skill, fantasy, will, etc) discriminated because of their skin color to take position where they "fit", according to their marginal productivity. To put it in another way, a productive society must select people according to qualities connected to marginal product, and skin color is not one of those: hence skin color cannot be treated systematically as a qualification for a job, if a society wants to be productive. Since fair equality of opportunity is in place, and this forbids the arbitrary exclusions of people meeting (what in a given social arrangement counts as) the relevant qualifications for position (whatever these happen to be, in a society), a just society cannot simply afford treating skin color as a qualification. The same reasoning cannot probably be done for a property such as deafness and shortness. A society can probably systematically discriminate people that have such traits, place them in the least rewarding social roles, and justify this via increased productivity to the very people it discriminate against, as there could be no way to reduce this discrimination without worsening deaf and short people's expectations of wealth and income.


Two conclusion follow:
A. being not-deaf and being not-short may both qualify as Rawlsian talents
B. a society in which the worst off members of society are all deaf and short might be just according to Rawls's criteria.

The only way from escaping this conclusion, it might seem, is to introduce the social basis of self-respect in the index we use to measure who is the worst off in society. Self-respect is indeed a primary good according to Rawls, but Rawls uses only income and wealth to evaluate social positions. And for good reasons: it is very difficult to measure trade-offs between a good such as self-respect and goods such as income and wealth. So the way out of the difficulty seems very difficult one to take.

Rawls and talents: first reflection

1. It is highly unlikely that the color of the skin could be treated as a talent in a society governed by just institutions. For our knowledge of production and exchange tells us that it is highly unlikely that a society where the color of a person's skin is treated as a relevant qualification for a social position could be governed by non-improvable institutions - meaning, institutions that produce the least inequality compatible with a certain level of wealth for the worst off members of it. In fact, it is easy to think that racial discrimination prevents people having the capacity to increase the total cake of goods for society from being matched with the social positions where they would acquire the ability to do so. If that is true, it follows that by forbidding employers to treat race as a relevant "qualification" in assigning positions of responsibility, the society can easily increase its total wealth. And this suggest that it might be possible to improve the position of the worst off by simply placing in key social positions the more talented people that were prevented from getting there by racial discrimination and placing the less talented ones in their place. This would increase the distributable wealth without necessarily requiring more incentives for the more talented, hence reducing inequality without damaging the goods available to the worst off members. If one considers self-respect, beside wealth, it is even clearer that racial origin can never be treated as a talent in a society fulfilling the overall scheme of Rawlsian institutions.

Rawls and talents: second reflection

2. There is no necessary guarantee that qualities that are found to be talents in a certain culture will be Rawlsian talents. Rawlsian talents are incompatible with Walzer's idea that the movement of social goods must be determined by their meaning (as found within a culture). For the conjunction of the following two propositions violates the idea that social goods are moved according to their meaning:

1. it is part of the meaning of some social goods (e.g. esteem) that they are allocated to the most talented

2. talents are not traits to which certain cultural meanings are attached, but they are Rawlsian talents

For if talents are Rawlsian talents, then whether they are talents or not depends on facts about possible distributions of primary goods in society. So the allocation of goods such as esteem depends on facts about possible distributions of primary social goods in society. This establishes what Walzer would call a "dominance" of the good "primary social good" over the good "esteem":the allocation of esteem depends (ultimately) upon the allocation of primary social goods.

Rawls and talents

What does it mean to be "more talented" in the context of Rawls's theory? As Nozick remarks (in a footnote of his discussion of Rawls' Theory - in Anarchy State and Utopia), "most talented" individuals just means, in the contexts of Rawls theory, those who are able to produce a larger economic output or who happen to be able to trade their work more favorably or to obtain social positions connected to the highest responsibilities and powers. The most talented should not be conceived to be such "from birth". Nothing must count as a talent absolutely - prior or independently from institutional arrangements. It follows that it is the ongoing scheme of cooperation that establishes whether some quality (or lack of it), say, the ability to speak backwards, or physical strength, corresponds to a talent (or lack of it). "Being talented" is a predicate that has a meaning only relative to a social arrangement.

I will now determine some properties that some quality must have in order to be a talent in a society that is just (according to Rawls). That is I will determine a necessary condition for something to be a talent in a Rawlsian society. A society is just, according to Rawls, if its basic structure (the main institutions that govern the distributions of social advantages and burdens) satisfies the following criteria:

1. Each person has an equal claim to a fully adequate scheme of
equal basic rights and liberties, which scheme is compatible with
the same scheme for all; and in this scheme the equal political
liberties, and only those liberties, are to be guaranteed their fair
value.

2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are
both:
(a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent
with the just savings principle, and
(b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions
of fair equality of opportunity.

The principle of fair equality of opportunity (b) says that:
Those with similar abilities and skills should have similar life chances. More specifically, assuming that there is a distribution of natural assets, those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have the same willingness to use them, should have the same prospects of success regardless of their initial place in
the social system.

On the basis of these two principles, we can define conditions that something must satisfy to count as a talent within a just society (a Rawlsian talent):

Being good (or bad) at F counts as a Rawlsian talent (or the lack of one) only if

institutions I [which ensure that people who have F and who make the same efforts to cultivate and use F have the same chance to end up occupying social positions connected to similar powers and prerogatives] belong to a scheme of institutions SI such that
- SI guarantees the basic liberties; and
- all the inequalities SI allows go to the advantage of the worst off representative individuals of that society;

That is to say, being good (or bad) at F counts as a Rawlsian talent (or the lack of one) only if the institutions ensuring equal chances to occupy social positions to those with equal talents and efforts are part of a regime of institutions in which social inequalities connected to social positions go to the advantage of the worst off (that is, a society in which no inequality could be eliminated without making the prospects of the worst off members even worst) and in which the basic liberties are respected.

What determines whether some trait which satisfies this necessary condition is eventually a talent, that is a good trait? The answer is: the free decisions of the people living within just institutions. A sufficient and necessary condition for a trait to count as a Rawlsian talent could therefore be the following:

F is a Rawlsian talent iff

the having of F by an individual is positively correlated to F's owner occupying offices and positions attached to responsibilities and powers, in a society governed by a scheme of institution SI where:

- people who have F and who make the same efforts to cultivate and use F have the same chance to end up occupying social positions connected to similar powers and prerogatives
- SI guarantees the basic liberties; and
- SI does not produce any inequality that could be eliminated without reducing the life-prospects of the least better-off members of society

This leads to the following three reflections:
first reflection
second reflection
third reflection